Thursday, November 17, 2011

On God and Grammar

Wayne Proudfoot (not to be confused with the Proudfeet hobbits in Tolkien’s Shire) makes the argument in Religious Experience that grammar constitutes our conception of God, specifically his attribute of ineffability. It is not uncommon among religious traditions to find the attribute of ineffability ascribed to deities or moral thingamabobs like, for example, the Tao. Anselm’s “God is that than which nothing greater can be thought” and Aquinas’ esse in his account of Divine Simplicity fall into this category. God used in this sense acts as what Proudfoot calls a ‘place-holder,’ since the very ineffability of “God-ness” fails to function as a pure referent.

Aquinas is particularly clear that we cannot actually talk about the essence of God. Our language is insufficient. At best we can only do one of two things: 1.) identify negative differentia and 2.) employ positive differentia, that is, analogous properties of what God might be like. Negative differentia are things which God is not. He is not a stone, a train, a story, a concept, an abstraction, etc. On the other hand, He is like some things. He is something like “Love,” something like our “Father,” something like “the Good.” Aquinas fears that to reduce God to anthropomorphic terms is to remove our sense of His otherness. (If my Aquinas is rusty, forgive me; it’s been 3 or so years.)

In other words, God as a symbol is not a referent to an actual object. There is no correspondence. Weird, right? Some religious theorists have taken issue with this characterization, saying that it is a form of intellectual laziness or simply bad logic. To refer to an object which cannot be referred to is nothing short of nonsense.

Proudfoot, however, makes an interesting play, positioning himself somewhere between Aquinas and these other religious theorist. In a sort of quasi-Wittgensteinian move, God in use has a function distinguishable from a referent and acquitted from being nonsensical. God’s very ineffability functions to produce a sense of otherness in His believers. How? Ineffability has a ritual and belief function determined by grammar. The grammatical backdrop inherent to theological paradigms provides the belief in God’s ineffability, and that ineffability functions as a catalyst for a belief in His mystery. In order to maintain a sense of the mysterious, theologians have included ineffability within their definition of God. Thus Aquinas says exactly what he means, and his characterization of God is not nonsensical.

Whether Proudfoot is right is beyond me. Much needs to be said about Proudfoot’s sneaky psychological evaluation of our theologian’s motives. Likewise, much needs to be said about whether grammar can produce the meaning of ineffability independent of religious experience, or whether, as another option, a priori categories of God might be determined by Calvin’s sensus divinitatis. Really, the question is whether the ineffability of God can be reduced to linguistic categories in the way Nietzsche construes the “leaf is the cause of leaf” problem. When does language constitute and create categories and when does it not? What I can say is that his approach is symptomatic of all things philosophy of language in the past century. Or to put it differently, his approach is nifty and I kinda like it.

7 comments:

Dave Strobolakos said...

It fascinates me how the issue of logical divine reference still occupies pages in theological works. Currently, I am working through a piece by Khaled Anatolios (Boston College) on the development of Trinitarian terminology/doctrine in light of the 4th century Arian controversy. These 3rd and 4th cent. theologians also hesitated to ascribe any positive predications about the essence of the 'unbegotten' God. Subsequently, they reverted to apophatic demarcations in order to create some linguistic pool to work with. I still can't help but like to think that God - in essence - is knowable; that when we talk about God we are referencing who he actually is. Unfortunately, that inclination puts me at odds with the majority of historical/traditional Christianity.

KevinsBlog said...

Dave, i remember the first time you and i were exposed to Divine Simplicity. We stood on different ground then, and we stand on different ground now ;-) I only recently discovered the apophatic tradition of Pseudo-Dionysius. It be interesting to see Aquinas' and Anselm's relationship to him. If you get the chance, enlighten me.

As for the knowability of God, the deeper study i do of language and phenomenology the less i like to even hear the word "know." It's not a helpful term. I'm more comfortable with "believe". In any case, thanks for reading. I hope and trust you're having a blast in grad school.

Ron Krumpos said...

We cannot rationally conceive of divine essence, but we can have a conscious intuition of being in it.

E=mc², Einstein's Special Theory of Relativity, is probably the best known scientific equation. I revised it to help better understand the relationship between divine Essence (Love, Grace, Spirit), matter (mass/energy: visible/dark) and consciousness (f(x) raised to its greatest power). Unlike the speed of light, which is a constant, there are no exact measurements for consciousness. In this hypothetical formula, basic consciousness may be of insects, to the second power of animals and to the third power the rational mind of humans. The fourth power is suprarational consciousness of mystics, when they intuit the divine essence in perceived matter. This was a convenient analogy, but there cannot be a divine formula.

(quoted from my free ebook, "the greatest achievement in life," on comparative mysticism)

KevinsBlog said...

Ron, thanks for reading. It is not clear to me what you mean by 'intuition of being in it.' Likewise the relational meaning you want to draw between matter and religious or, if you prefer, mystical experience. Any number of religious persons would specifically want to identify religious experience as separable from physical objects, or 'perceived matter.' The same problem arises in light of questions surrounding the being (in the ontological sense)of divine essence, where that essence is specifically believed to be non-corporeal.

Ron Krumpos said...

Kevin, we both know the limitations of words, but let me try to use some to clarify what I had written.

Ontologically, mystics have - on occasion -direct experience or intuition of divine Essence, ultimate Reality and absolute Truth. Not many theologians, scientists or philosophers would agree that is even possible, but then they seldom agree on anything.

My use of E, m and c from the Special Theory was merely a simplistic analogy, not meant to be fact. That hypothetical formula should no be taken too far.

KevinsBlog said...

Ron, religious philosophers and theorists do not disagree that the experience is possible, that is phenomenological, they disagree about whether it corresponds to something real, that is, ontological. The trouble, of course, is that phenomenological experience is non-falsifiable. I can no more tell a mystic that his experience doesn't appear real to him than i can tell you that you are not on your computer right now. But what appears to be the case and what is the case are two orders of inquiry. Religious theorists like Proudfoot are generally unconcerned with ontological questions, though, of course, they will have informed opinions of the matter: opinions which, in turn, guide their argument.Proudfoot, for example, probably hopes to reduce mystical experience to some kind of naturalistic account-- likely psychological-- but he is never explicate. And his reticence is not an exception among theorists, it is the rule.

Ron Krumpos said...

My MA was in Philosophy (a long time ago) and my thesis was on Existentialism vs. Vedanta. I also took a course in Phenomenology (Husserl, not Heidegger). I stick to my conviction that a mystic has a conscious ontological intuition...awareness of the ground of being as it is. As you say, however, that is non-falsifiable. I cannot prove it rationally and others cannot disprove it (even though they may strenuously disagree).

I conduct an email forum for professors who teach mysticism at universities on six continents. Wayne Proudfoot is on my mailing list, but has never responded. Fortunately, some of the most prominent scholars writing on mysticism today have actively taken part (although I wish more of them would). My ebook and that forum have provided me with stimulating retirement activities.